دیوید میلر (1942-2024) : مدافع بی باک حقیقت
David William Miller, who passed away on Wednesday, 20 November 2024, at the age of 82, was a great epistemologist, philosopher of science and philosopher of logic. He was also one of Karl Popper’s closest assistants, disciples, and colleagues, and, as his webpage on Wikipedia informs us, a ‘prominent exponent of critical rationalism’.
David Miller became acquainted with Popper in 1964 when he enrolled at the Department of Logic and Scientific Method at the London School of Economics and Political Science. While completing his Master’s degree, Popper invited him to become his assistant. This relationship soon turned into a long-life close friendship in which critical dialogues between the teacher and the young student exemplified Popper’s most favourite motto, namely, “I may be wrong and you may be right, and by an effort, we may get nearer to the truth”. Popper used to discuss his ideas with his assistant, who later became his colleague, as fellow philosopher of science, and benefit from his penetrating observations. As just one example among many other, more or less similar cases, Miller played a particularly important role in assisting Popper with his ‘Replies to my Critics’ in P. A. Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of Karl Popper (1974).
Upon graduating from LSE, Miller moved to the University of Warwick and joined the Department of Philosophy there, initially as an instructor, soon to become a Lecturer (Assistant Professor) in the philosophy of logic and later a Reader (Associate Professor). While at Warwick, he produced scores of highly informative and insightful papers, book chapters, reviews, two influential books (Critical Rationalism: A Restatement and Defence 1994, and Out of Error 2006), and edited an important anthology of Popper’s published works (Popper’s Selections 1985). Among his latest papers was “Logical Content and Its Malcontents” which was published in this Journal (Volume 17, Issue 42 , June 2023, Pages 281-297, https://doi.org/10.22034/jpiut.2023.16588).
One of the key aims of this impressive array of scholarly publications was to explain and elucidate the finer details of critical rationalism, and further develop this system of thought and way of life that had been introduced by Popper through his various works. Another important objective of Miller’s papers and books was to correct Popper’s mistakes and incomplete arguments.
One of the most famous cases of correcting Popper’s mistakes concerns Popper’s effort to introduce characterising the relative verisimilitude (nearness to the truth) of rival theories. But as soon as Popper published his proposed criterion in 1974, Miller published a paper in the same journal (The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science) and argued that it would not be possible to characterise their nearness to the truth by logical means as Popper had suggested. Miller’s argument was eloquent and succinct: he argued that to show a theory T2 is closer to the truth than a theory T1, one should show either the falsity content of T1 is larger than the falsity content of T2, assuming that the truth contents are equal, or the truth content of T2 is larger than the truth content of T1 assuming that their falsity content is equal. In either case, by making use of two simple logical apparatuses, he demonstrated that since the true or false consequences that can be derived from each theory are infinite, their content cannot be compared.
Popper acknowledged his mistake but suggested that despite the failure of his technical effort, the basic heuristic notion of his proposal was on the right track.
Another case, from among a good number of cases, where Miller corrected Popper’s somewhat inaccurate formulation of his own thought was when Popper, despite his uncompromising anti-inductivist position, perhaps as a concession to his critics, stated that there may have been “a whiff of inductivism” in his reasoning concerning a famous argument about the progress in science known as ‘The Miracle Argument’. This argument simply states that if a theory T2 (say Einstein's theory of relativity) fares better than a theory T1 (say Newton’s theory of gravity) with respect to the empirical data, then the more successful theory should contain some truth about reality; otherwise its success would be a miracle. Popper wrote: “… [T]here may be a 'whiff’ of inductivism here; It enters with the vague realist assumption that reality, though unknown, is in some respects similar to what science tells us or, in other words, with the assumption that science can progress towards greater verisimilitude”. Miller, in his clarification of Popper’s point, after taking his reader through some mildly technical points, stated that “even if the empirical success of a theory did raise the probability that that theory was near the truth, we would not have an inductive effect on our hands. It would be a probabilistic effect; but, … there is really nothing inductive about probabilistic support” (Miller, Critical Rationalism: A Restatement and Defence, 1994, 47).
Miller’s prose was insightful but always succinct and to the point, distilled of all extra, not absolutely necessary, information, with an undercurrent of sardonic wit. Unfortunately, it seems the succinctness of his arguments cost him dearly: many of his critics who tried to counter his arguments, perhaps unbeknown to themselves, demonstrated that they did not understand the subtle points he had tried to put across.
At a personal level, Miller was deeply moral, unfailingly kind towards his friends and students, and generous with his time with regard to responding to the questions his readers would put to him from all over the world. He was an engaging teacher, though outside of the classroom, he was a private individual who would readily admit that he was not a public speaker.
After his retirement, Miller made several visits to South America, and was energetic in his intellectual support of people there interested in critical rationalism.
His intellectual legacy, part of which he had made available to scholars through his webpage at Warwick University (https://warwick.ac.uk/fac/soc/philosophy/people/miller) and part of which has remained unpublished and is hoped that it will see the light of the day in due course, is, just like the legacy of his teacher, Karl Popper, full of interesting and insightful ideas which can be developed by those who care to study them.
Miller is survived by his two sons, Alexander and James, and two grandsons, Oscar and Tommy.
Ali Paya
Ian Charles Jarvie
(8th July 1937-16th May 2023)
(Picture: Courtesy of Mrs. Pam Shearmur)
Ian Jarvie, of whose death we have just heard, was a remarkable man. He studied anthropology at the London School of Economics as an undergraduate, and then wrote his Ph.D., under Karl Popper, applying a Popperian approach to issues in anthropology. (See his The Revolution in Anthropology.) This work offers not only an interesting theoretical treatment of problems in anthropology to do with cargo cults. It offers also a sustained discussion and appraisal of Popper’s methodological ideas in the context of concrete issues in the social sciences. The Revolution in Anthropology was followed by other volumes tackling related topics, such as Concepts and Society and Rationality and Relativism.
After a Period working as Popper’s assistant at the L.S.E., Jarvie took up a position at the University of Hong Kong, later moving to York University, Toronto, where he remained for the rest of his career. In Hong Kong, he became involved in fruitful life-long collaboration with Joseph Agassi (whom he had known from the L.S.E.). This led to papers on such topics as ‘The Rationality of Magic’; to their many-volume edition of Ernest Gellner’s papers; to their collection Rationality: The Critical View; and to their joint book on Critical Rationalist Aesthetics. Jarvie was also editor, with Sandra Pralong, of Popper’s Open Society after 50 Years and – with Karl Milford and David Miller – of the wide-ranging three-volume collection, Karl Popper: A Centenary Assessment.
Jarvie’s own book, The Republic of Science, is worth particular mention as offering a striking partly social interpretation of Popper’s epistemology.
Not only did Jarvie write extensively on issues to do with anthropology and critical rationalism (especially on the philosophy of social science). But he wrote also numerous articles, and published several books, on the sociology and philosophy of film, including Philosophy of the Film: Epistemology, Ontology, Aesthetics. (See, for a list of Jarvie’s extensive publications: https://jarvie.info.yorku.ca/files/2019/01/ListofPublications.pdf?x48812)
In addition to all this, Jarvie played a key role as managing editor of the major journal Philosophy of the Social Sciences, of which he was one of the founders. This journal was significant not only as the locus of debates in the philosophy of social science, but also because of the various exchanges that it contained on issues to do with critical rationalism more generally.
Jarvie was a man of considerable achievement, but of great modesty. He played a really important role in the development of critical rationalism in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries. He will be sorely missed.
His article in this journal:
Popper’s Sociology of Science and Its Political Deficit ( https://philosophy.tabrizu.ac.ir/article_16582.html?lang=en)
Robert Stern (1962-2024)
His interests included figures such as Kant, Kierkegaard, Murdoch, Levinas, Peirce and Luther. He provided original interpretations of complex and sometimes confusing philosophical arguments. Bob was best known for reintroducing neglected figures from the history of philosophy. Hegel was the first among these.
Before the 1980s, Hegel was regarded with scorn by some analytic philosophers, representing all that was wrong with what they disparagingly called continental philosophy. Through meticulous reconstruction of Hegel’s arguments, Bob recovered a Hegel who was not only intelligible but also remarkably interesting and credible. Neither dogmatist nor mystic, his Hegel offers a holistic metaphysics, which recognises both the achievements of reason and the crucial value of tradition and ordinary morality.
He also played a key role in reviving international interest in KE Løgstrup, who, although “world-famous in Denmark” (as Bob used to joke), had been largely ignored in English-speaking philosophy until he published his 2019 book The Radical Demand in Løgstrup’s Ethics.
Born in Norwich, Bob was the son of Jack, who ran a jewellery shop, and Isabel (nee Cohen). Bob went to Gresham’s school in Holt, Norfolk, and studied philosophy at St John’s College, Cambridge for his BA and PhD, before taking up a post in the philosophy department at Sheffield University in 1989, where he was my doctoral supervisor.
He was made a professor in 2000 and served as chair of the Philosophy Research Excellence Framework Panel, as president of the Aristotelian Society and the British Philosophical Association, and as editor of the European Journal of Philosophy and the Hegel Bulletin. He was also president of the British Society for the History of Philosophy and was elected a fellow of the British Academy in 2019.
Bob enthusiastically supported student initiatives (including Philosophy in the City, an outreach programme) and spearheaded the yearly Philosophy Rocks! concert (probably inspired by his love for Bob Dylan), during which philosophy students and staff play music together.
He met his wife, Crosby (nee Stevens), while they were students at Cambridge, and they married in 1988. They made their home in Sheffield, where he was a stalwart presence at the weekly Endcliffe parkrun.
He is survived by Crosby and their children, Adam and Lucy.
Joshua Forstenzer