Journal of Philosophical Investigations

نوع مقاله : مقاله علمی- پژوهشی

نویسنده

Professor of Social Ethics, School X Newcastle University, United Kingdom

چکیده

Commentators oft cite the rather grand claim that for Hegel there was no concept of individual personality, subjectivity nor personal autonomy in Ancient Greece. Hegel’s claim is either taken as orthodox and making sense in the Hegelian historical system as a whole and so little discussed; or is flatly ignored as the worst kind of metaphysical obfuscation; a response a little too comfortable for liberal thinkers. Neither reaction is entirely satisfying. Not enough attention has been paid to it, especially for the vast majority of social and political thinkers who would find it at least contentious, so the present paper aims to assert its significance both for Hegelian politics as a whole and to pay enough attention to it in order to make it very difficult for those who find it a contentious statement to continue to ignore it. One wants to ask what it might mean for one’s self-understanding to be so radically different that, as a human being, I understand myself as first and foremost (and perhaps completely) not as a subjective individual. It is conceptually very difficult to be a self-conscious individual -- in even a minimal sense -- without some idea of being an atomic, individual unit. It is the claim of the following argument that a full understanding of this distinction, between ancient and modern self-understandings, would lead to a revision of Hegel’s liberal credentials, though not entirely for liberal reasons.

کلیدواژه‌ها

عنوان مقاله [English]

Hegel, the Greeks and Subjectivity: the origins of modern liberty and the historical justification of liberalism

نویسنده [English]

  • David Edward Rose

Professor of Social Ethics, School X Newcastle University, United Kingdom

چکیده [English]

Commentators oft cite the rather grand claim that for Hegel there was no concept of individual personality, subjectivity nor personal autonomy in Ancient Greece. Hegel’s claim is either taken as orthodox and making sense in the Hegelian historical system as a whole and so little discussed; or is flatly ignored as the worst kind of metaphysical obfuscation; a response a little too comfortable for liberal thinkers. Neither reaction is entirely satisfying. Not enough attention has been paid to it, especially for the vast majority of social and political thinkers who would find it at least contentious, so the present paper aims to assert its significance both for Hegelian politics as a whole and to pay enough attention to it in order to make it very difficult for those who find it a contentious statement to continue to ignore it. One wants to ask what it might mean for one’s self-understanding to be so radically different that, as a human being, I understand myself as first and foremost (and perhaps completely) not as a subjective individual. It is conceptually very difficult to be a self-conscious individual -- in even a minimal sense -- without some idea of being an atomic, individual unit. It is the claim of the following argument that a full understanding of this distinction, between ancient and modern self-understandings, would lead to a revision of Hegel’s liberal credentials, though not entirely for liberal reasons.

کلیدواژه‌ها [English]

  • Hegel
  • person
  • individual personality
  • subjectivity
  • autonomy
  • Ancient Greece
  • liberal
  • liberalism
Berlin, I. (2002). The birth of individualism: a turning-point in the history of political thought. Liberty. Edited by H. Hardy. Oxford University Press.
Knowles, D. (1990). The Right to Private Property. The Philosophical Quarterly, 40(158), 116-119.
Faris, E. (1914). The Origin of Punishment. International Journal of Ethics, 25(1), 54-67.
Farneth, M. (2013). Gender and the Ethical Given. Journal of Religious Ethics, 41(4), 643–667.
Fleischman, E. (1971). The Role of the Individual in Pre-revolutionary Society: Stirner, Marx, and Hegel.” In Pelczynski, Z. (1971). Hegel's Political Philosophy Problems and Perspectives: a Collection of New Essays. Cambridge University Press.
Foucault, M. (1978). About the Concept of the ‘Dangerous Individual in 19th-Century Legal Psychiatry. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry. 1.(1), 1–18.
Franco, P. (1997). Hegel and Liberalism. The Review of Politics. 59(4), 831-860.
Harris, H. (1993). Hegel’s intellectual development to 1807. In Cambridge Companion to Hegel. Edited by F. Beiser. Cambridge University Press.
Hegel, G. (2006). Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion: One volume edition, the lectures of 1827, translated by R. Brown, P. Hodgson; & J. Stewart. University of California Press.
Hegel, G. (1999). On the Scientific Ways of Treating Natural Law, on its Place in Moral Philosophy, and its Relation to the Positive Sciences of Right, trans. H. Nisbet. Political Writings, Cambridge University Press.
Hegel, G. (1991a). Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Translated by H. Nisbet. Cambridge University Press.
Hegel, G. (1991b). Philosophy of History. Translated by J. Sibree. Prometheus Books.
Hegel, G. (1999c). The Encyclopaedia Logic: Part 1 of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze, trans. T. Geraets, A. Suchting, & H. Harris. Indianapolis, USA: Hackett Publishing Co.
Hegel, G. (1986). Nurnberger Propadeutik, Werke in 20 Bänden mit Registerband - 4: Nürnberger und Heidelberger Schriften 1808–1817. Suhrkamp Verlag.
Hegel, G. (1979). System of Ethical Life, translated by T. Knox & H. Harris. State University of NewYork Press.
Hegel, G. (1977). The Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A. Miller. Oxford University Press.
Hegel, G. (1975). Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art. Translated by T. Knox. Clarendon Press.
Hegel, G. (1971). Philosophy of Mind: Part 3 of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences with the Zusätze, translated by W. Wallace & A. Miller. Oxford University Press.
Hegel, G. (1955). Lectures of the HIstory of Philosophy. Vol.3. Translated by E. Haldane. Routledge.
Hegel, Charles & Bryant, W. (1878). Hegel on Classic Art, The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 12(2), 145-160.
Herder, J. (2004). Another Philosophy of History and Selected Political Writings. Translated by I.  Evrigenis and D. Pellerin, Hackett Publishing Company.
Hobbes, T. (1991). Man and Citizen: De Homine and De Cive. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing.
Joyce, T. A. (2013). South American Archaeology: an introduction to the archaeology of the south american continent with special reference to the early history of Peru. Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason. Edited by P. Guyer and A. Wood, Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (1991). An Answer to the Question: What is Enlightenment?  In Political Writings. Translated by H. Nisbet. Edited by H. Reiss. Cambridge University Press.
Laitinen, A. (2017). Hegel and Respect for Persons. In The Roots of Respect. Edited by G. Giorgini & E. Irrera. De Gruyter.
Mackay, L. A. (1962). Antigone, Coriolanus, and Hegel. Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association, 93, 166., doi:10.2307/283759.
Neuhouser, F. (2003). Hegel’s Social Theory: Actualizing Freedom. Harvard University Press.
O'Neill, O. (1990). Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy. Cambridge University Press.
Pelczynski, Z. A. (1971). Hegel's Political Philosophy Problems and Perspectives; a Collection of New Essays. Cambridge University Press.
Pelczynski, Z. A. (1971). Political Community and Individual Freedom in Hegel’s Philosophy of State. in The State and the Civil Society: Studies in Hegel’s Political Philosophy. Edited by. Z. A. Pelczynski. Cambridge University Press.
Pietercil, R. (1978). Antigone and Hegel. International Philosophical Quarterly, 18(3), 289–310.
Pinkard, T. (2017). Does History Make Sense? Hegel on the Historical Shapes of Justice. Harvard University Press.
Pinkard, T. (2001). Hegel: a Biography. Cambridge University Press.
Rawls, J. (1999). The Idea of Public Reason Revisited. Collected papers. Harvard University Press.
Rawls, J. (1993). Political Liberalism.  Columbia University Press.
Rose, D. (2019). Tracing the subjectivities of the changing human: Hegel, self-understanding and posthuman objective freedom. Journal of Posthuman Studies: Philosophy, Technology, Media. 2(2), 190-212.
Rose, D. (2009). Free Will and Continental Philosophy: the Death without Meaning. Continuum.
Seade, E. D. D. (1979). State and History in Hegel's Concept of People. Journal of the History of Ideas. 40(3) (1979): 369-384.
Smith, A. (2010). The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Penguin.
Singer, P. (2001). Hegel: a Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press.
Sophocles. (2008). The Theban Plays: Oedipus the King, Oedipus at Colonus, Antigone. Translated by R. Fainright and R. Littman. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.
Stern, R. (1998). Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit and Logic. Routledge.
Stewart, J. (2018). The Egyptian Religion. Oxford Scholarship Online, doi:10.1093/oso/9780198829492.003.0008.
Stewart, J. (2017). Hegel and the Egyptian Religion as a Mystery or Enigma: the inner and the outer. Filosofia. 72(1), 54-63.
Taylor, Ch. (2018). Hegel. Cambridge University Press.
Tierney, M. (1923). The Greeks and Ourselves. An Irish Quarterly Review. 12(46). 261-272.
Velkley, R. (2006). On Possessed Individualism: Hegel, Socrates' Daimon, and the Modern State. The Review of Metaphysics. 59(3), 577-599.
Wood, A. (2002). Hegel's Ethical Thought. Cambridge University Press.
CAPTCHA Image